I've posted on memory a few different times, but thus far I've shied away from going into great molecular detail; in fact, I've pretty much avoided molecular and cellular neuroscience altogether on this "blog." This sidestepping results, to be honest, from laziness; it is easier to make gambling and ventriloquism widely appealing than it is to spice up intracellular mechanisms like gene regulation and protein folding, although I believe the latter two are actually quite intriguing and wholly relevant to understanding the mind.
Glossing over molecular details is actually somewhat at odds with my attitude towards neuroscience, a field which has appealed to me since middle school because it links causal, physical mechanisms with delightfully wondrous things like memorizing pieces of music (the actual moment of inspiration occurred while I was playing the piano). Since then, I have been fascinated by the idea that the biology--proteins, molecules, genes etc--of individual cells is directly related to the complexities of human thought, from kicking a soccer ball and catching a dodgeball to learning a language and dreaming.
In the days since middle school, however, I've come to realize that by attempting to bridge molecules to behavior, neuroscience is both marvelously exciting and incredibly problematic. In between these two levels are, in increasing levels of organization: the cellular, the intercellular (synaptic), the circuit (networks/pathways), the regional (e.g. fMRI studies), and the systems (e.g. motor systems), and a wide range of inter-level hierarchies upon which I won't begin to touch. Because of the enormous distance one must travel from specific molecules to the human mind, many cognitive neuroscientists dismiss "reductionism" as analyzing mechanisms which are too far removed from behavior to be directly relevant; they believe each level must be bridged before making any larger connections.
I agree that the mind cannot be understood by looking solely at the simplest biological components, but I also feel that knowledge of neural networks, etc., is meaningless unless we understand the biological basis. In other words, the cellular approach is necessary, but not sufficient, for understanding the brain. Most cognitive processes, in particular memory formation, have much to gain from molecular and cellular analyses.
Memory formation is endlessly fascinating on all levels. Conceptually, memory is (to quote Eric Kandel), "a form of mental time travel [which] frees us from the constraints of time and space"; mechanistically, it is a result of the brain's ability to embody, retain, and modify information in neural circuits. To further define 'memories' using neuronally (i.e. biologically)-relevant vocabulary, it is helpful to distinguish it from closely-related 'knowledge' and 'learning.'
'Knowledge,' in neuronal terms, is the perceived world converted into a neuronal form; it exists as "internal representations." These representations issue from the activity and connectivity of neurons (forming an assembly of neurons: a 'neural circuit'), and is thus inextricably linked to the biological properties of those neurons, particularly of their functional interconnections (i.e. synapses).
'Learning' is then the experience-dependent creation or modification of these internal representations; i.e. changes in the way the neurons are connected to each other in specific circuits, particularly the strength of their synapses ('synaptic plasticity'). 'Memory' is thus the retention of the aforementioned experience-dependent modifications. The salient idea is that specific biological properties must be altered, (in particular, those of the synapse) in order for memory to be established; moreover, these properties are products of universal cellular and molecular mechanisms that are employed throughout the body and the living world.
(So what are these cellular and molecular mechanisms? For those in need of some scientific background information on neuronal communication, this site is quite clear and comprehensive, or for a briefer version I've given a summary here.)
And now, leaping and bounding back through the conceptual hierarchy of neuroscience, these biological processes are linked to functional changes occurring within neural circuits, which latter ultimately guide behavior. Thus, although reductionist techniques attempt to experimentally link molecules directly to behavior, the overarching theoretical goal involves bridges between and amongst all levels. Modern molecular techniques are all the more powerful when combined with other levels of analyses: after intervening at the cellular or molecular level, well-accepted psychological and behavioral paradigms can be employed to determine whether a given biological process is correlated with (or necessary, or perhaps even sufficient for) the occurrence of a behavioral phenomenon.
One elegant example of the power of reductionism (which motivated this post, in particular the somewhat lyrical wax of an introduction) was just published online in Nature Neuroscience. The study, carried out by a group from UT Southwestern, manipulated a neuronal protein to assess its role in learning and memory, thus attempting to bridge the behavioral and the molecular pathway levels directly. I will go into more detail on the paper, and the neurobiology of memory, in the following post.
Friday, June 1, 2007
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
6 comments:
Interesting - is this partially a response to my criticisms of reductionism? :)
"I also feel that knowledge of neural networks, etc., is meaningless unless we understand the biological basis."
I think we agree on this (in fact, I am interested in "neural networks" only insofar as they *are* a biological basis of mind) but we may disagree on what actually constitutes a biological "basis" (and in fact, this is the crux of the complaint against reductionism).
How low is low enough? You think the systems level is too high, so let's talk cellular. Oops, now we need to talk molecular too, b/c cellular functioning is ultimately tied to the interaction of molecular signals. Uh-oh, now we also need to understand the genetic basis of those signals. Hmmm - it turns out that the genetic basis of the molecular basis of the cellular basis of the systems basis of cognition also involves an understanding of Van der Waals forces, and an ever-descending spiral of levels of analysis (all the way down to the quantum level, accd to some). The point is: how brutally do we have to break apart Humpty Dumpty before we can start putting him back together again?
This is a question that reductionism, on its own, *cannot* answer.
Heya Chris,
I agree with you: that there is a risk in degenerating down the reductionism spiral until the overarching goal has all but vanished. This has always been a dilemma for me with respect to neuroscience, and unfortunately I haven't found a solution. For me, it arises out of a fundamental incommensurability: between a desire to fully explain the physical basis of the mind, and a desire to understand the most complex products of the human mind. These two desires take me in opposite directions, and unfortunately there is no satisfying middle ground (for me).
In neuroscience research, I believe everyone has to find their own boundary, such that they can address a fulfilling level of complexity (from decision making and reflexes to LTP and depolarization) to a convincing level of biological detail. I'm still struggling to find my own compromise of the conflicting goods and evils, in both my research and my writing.
Thus, more than anything, this post was somewhat therapeutic/cathartic for me...I was addressing my inadvertent, displeasing tendency, in the short history of my blog, to brush aside basic biology; I was worried I was giving an impression of disregard to the contributions of molecular and cellular neuroscience.
I read your post, and liked it, and did not disagree with it. I don't think reductionism can answer much about the mind on it's own, but neither can an fMRI study, or a simulated neural network, or a neural recording. All of these approaches contribute to the field, and the beauty of neuroscience is that if they pay enough attention to each other they can harmonize and be instrumental in reaching the all-embracing goal.
I do think that cognitive neuroscientists often fail to give molecular and cellular neuroscience the respect they deserve. Likewise, many of my colleagues in cell/molecular hold undue contempt for "systems-level" approaches, believing them to be messy and/or hollow (relative to their intensely consequential experiments of course), and they certainly could benefit by being a little more open minded.
Thanks for commenting!
I enjoyed this post, as I do most of your stuff - particularly in light of the flurry of recent posts by Chris C and Jonah L on memory - it seems to be making the rounds - so I referenced all you guys in a short post at my place - bookeywookey.
I guess the reason why the louis vuitton handbags named after the famous French theater is that besides their same classic Louis vuitton bags but modern appearance they have the same mission to bring life to the artistic heritage of Europe. The Odeon Theater carries forward the culture of opera and film while the Odeon GM bag promotes the culture of artistic design and louis vuitton Brand. Oscar Deutsch entertains our nation, but lv fashions our nation.
To be a adroit charitable being is to procure a kind of openness to the world, an ability to trust aleatory things beyond your own control, that can take you to be shattered in uncommonly extreme circumstances as which you were not to blame. That says something very important relating to the fettle of the principled life: that it is based on a trustworthiness in the uncertain and on a willingness to be exposed; it's based on being more like a shop than like a sparkler, something fairly feeble, but whose acutely item beauty is inseparable from that fragility.
off white nike
supreme clothing
off white
supreme hoodie
kevin durant shoes
kobe sneakers
bape t shirt
yeezy boost 350
kyrie 7
kd shoes
Post a Comment